检索规则说明:AND代表“并且”;OR代表“或者”;NOT代表“不包含”;(注意必须大写,运算符两边需空一格)
检 索 范 例 :范例一: (K=图书馆学 OR K=情报学) AND A=范并思 范例二:J=计算机应用与软件 AND (U=C++ OR U=Basic) NOT M=Visual
作 者:张大宇
出 处:《哲学进展》2024年第6期1352-1357,共6页Advances in Philosophy
摘 要:康德的因果关系理论直接来源于对休谟问题的回答,然而对于“康德的因果关系理论是否成功解决了休谟问题?”这件事情,学术界尚未形成定论。在笔者看来,休谟对因果关系的普遍必然性的否定是基于他的客观主义(即认为真理的对象是独立于人的客观世界)与经验主义(感官知觉是知识的唯一可靠的来源)的预设,在这种预设的前提下,证明因果关系的推理无法获得普遍必然性。而康德否定了休谟的预设,也改变了特殊因果性的概念内涵,反之以一种现象主义与先验论的立场来论证了因果关系的普遍必然性。Kant’s theory of causality is directly derived from his answer to the Hume’s problem. However, the academic community has not yet formed a consensus on whether Kant’s theory of causality has successfully solved the Hume’s problem. In the author’s view, Hume’s negation of the universal inevitability of causality is based on his assumptions of objectivism (that is, the object of truth is independent of the objective world of humans) and empiricism (sensory perception is the only reliable source of knowledge), under which reasoning to prove causality cannot obtain universal inevitability. Kant denied Hume’s presupposition and changed the concept of special causality. On the contrary, he argued for the universal inevitability of causality from a phenomenological and transcendental perspective.
正在载入数据...
正在载入数据...
正在载入数据...
正在载入数据...
正在载入数据...
正在载入数据...
正在载入数据...
正在链接到云南高校图书馆文献保障联盟下载...
云南高校图书馆联盟文献共享服务平台 版权所有©
您的IP:3.139.238.74